Tuesday, November 28, 2023

КЕНЕТ ВОЛТС: Теорија на меѓународната политика

6.

Anarchic Structures and Balances of Power

 

Two tasks remain: first, to examine the character of anarchy and the expectations about outcomes associated with anarchic realms; second, to examine the ways in which expectations vary as the structure of an anarchic system changes through changes in the distribution of capabilities across nations. The second task, undertaken in chapters 7,8 and 9, requires comparing different international systems. The first, which I now turn to, is best accomplished by drawing some comparisons between behavior and outcomes in anarchic and hierarchic realms.

 

I.

1. VIOLENCE AT HOME AND ABROAD

 

The state among the states, it is often said, conducts its affairs in the brooding shadow of violence. Because some states may at any time use force, all states must be prepared to do so – or live at the mercy of their military more vigorous neighbors. Among states, the state of nature is a state of war. This is meant not in the sense that war constantly occurs, but in the sense that, with each state deciding for itself whether or not to use force, war may at any time break out. Whether in the family, the community, or the world at large, contact without at least the occasional conflict is inconceivable; and the hope that in the absence of an agent to manage or to manipulate conflicting parties the use of force will always be avoided cannot be realistically entertained. Among men as among states, anarchy, or absence of government, is associated with the occurrence of violence.

The threat of violence and the recurrent use of force are said to distinguish international from national affairs. But in the history of the world, surely most rulers have had to bear in mind that their subjects might use force to resist or overthrow them. If the absence of government is associated with the threat of violence, so also is its presence. A haphazard list of national tragedies illustrates the point all too well. The most destructive wars of the hundred years following the defeat of Napoleon took place not among states but within them. Estimates of deaths in China’s Taiping Rebellion, which began on 1851 and lasted 13 years, range as high as 20 million. In the American Civil War some 600 thousand people lost their lives. In more recent history, forced collectivization and Stalin’s purges eliminated five million Russians, and Hitler exterminated six million Jews. In some Latin American countries, coups d’etats and rebellions have been normal features in national life. Between 1948 and 1957, for example, 200 thousand Colombians were killed in civil strife. In the middle 1970’s most inhabitants of Idi Amin’s Uganda must have felt their lives becoming nasty, brutish, and short, quite as in Thomas Hobbes’s state of nature. If such cases constitute aberrations, they are uncomfortably common ones. We easily lose sight of the fact that struggles to achieve and maintain power, to establish order, and to contrive a kind of justice within states, may be bloodier that wars among them.

If anarchy is identified with chaos, destruction and death, then the distinction between anarchy and government does not tell much. Which is more precarious: the life of a state among the states, or of government in relation to its subjects? The answer varies with time or place. Among some states at some times, the actual or expected occurrence of violence is low. Within some states at some times, the actual expected occurrence of violence is high. The use of force, or the constant fear of its use, are not sufficient grounds for distinguishing international from domestic affairs. If the possible and the actual use of force mark both national or international orders, then no durable distinction between the two realms can be drawn in terms of the use or the nonuse of force. No human order is proof against violence.

To discover qualitative differences between internal and external affairs one must look for a criterion other than the occurrence of violence. The distinction between international and national realms of politics is not found in the use of the nonuse of force but in their different structures. But if the dangers of being violently attacked is greater, say, in taking an evening stroll through downtown Detroit then they are in picnicking along the French and German border, what practical difference does the difference between of structure make? Nationally as internationally, contacts generates conflict and at time issues in violence. The difference between national and international politics lies not in the use of force but in the different modes of organization for doing something about it. A government, ruling by some standard of legitimacy, arrogates to itself the right to use force – that is, to apply a variety of sanctions to control the use of force by its subjects. If some use private force, other may appeal to the government. A government has no monopoly on the use of force, as is all too evident. An effective government, however, has a monopoly on the legitimate use of force, and legitimate here means that public agents are organized to prevent ant to counter the private use of force. Citizens need not to prepare to defend themselves. Public agencies do that. A national system is not one of self-help. The international system is.

 

2. INTERDEPENDANCE AND INTEGRATION

 

The political significance of interdependence varies depending on whether a realm is organized, with relations on authority specified and established, or remains formally unorganized. Insofar as a realm is formally organized, its units are free to specialize, to pursue their own interests without concern for developing the means of maintaining their identity and preserving their security in the presence of others. They are free to specialize because they have no reason to fear the increased interdependence that goes with specialization. If those who specialize most benefit most, then competition in specialization ensues. Goods are manufactured, grain is produced, law and order are maintained, commerce is conducted, and financial services are provided by people who ever more narrowly specialize. In simple economic terms, the cobbler depends on the tailor for his pants and the tailor on the cobbler for his shoes, and each would be ill-clad without services of the other. In simple political terms, Kansas depends on Washington for protection and regulation and Washington depends on Kansas for beef and wheat. In saying that in such situations interdependence is close, one need not maintain that the one part could not learn to live without the other. One need only say that the coast of breaking the interdependent relation would be high. Persons and institutions depend heavily on one another because of the different tasks they perform and the different goods they produce and exchange. The parts of a polity bind themselves together by their differences (cf. Durkheim 1893, p. 212).

Differences between national and international structures are reflected in the ways the units of each system define their ends and develop the means for reaching them. In anarchic realms, like units co-act. In hierarchic realm, the units are differentiated, and they tend to increase the extent of their specialization. Differentiated units become closely interdependent, the more closely so as their specialization proceeds. Because of the difference of the structure, interdependence within and interdependence among nations are two distinct concepts. So as to follow the logicians’ admonition to keep a single meaning for a given term throughout one’s discourse. I shall use “integration” to describe the condition within nations and “interdependence” to describe the condition among them.

Although states are like units functionally they differ vastly in their capabilities. Out of such differences something of a division of labor develops (see Chapter 9). The division of labor across nations, however, is slight in comparison with the highly articulated division of labor among them. Integration draws the parts of a nation closely together. Interdependence among nations leaves them loosely connected. Although the integration of the nations is often talked about, it seldom takes place. Nations could mutually enrich themselves by further dividing not just the labor that goes into the production of goods but also some of the other tasks they perform, such as political management and military defense. Who dos their integration not take place? The structure of international politics limits the cooperation of states in two ways.

In a self-help system each of the units spends a portion of its effort, not in forwarding its own good, but in providing the means of protection itself against others. Specialization in a system of divided labor works to everyone’s advantage, though not equally so. Inequality in expected distribution of the increased product works strongly against extension of the division of labor internationally. When faced with the possibility of cooperating for mutual gain, states that feel insecure must ask how the gain will be divided. They are compelled to ask not “Will both of us gain” but “Who will gain more?” If an expected gain is to be divided, say, in a ration of two to one, one state may use its disproportionate gain to implement a policy intended to damage or destroy the other. Even the prospect of large absolute gains for both parties does not elicit their cooperation so long as each fears how the other will use its increased capabilities. Notice that the impediments to collaboration may not lie in the character and the immediate intention of either party. Instead, the condition of insecurity – at the least, the uncertainty of each about the other’s future intentions and actions – works against their cooperation.

In any self-help system, units worry about their survival, and the worry conditions their behavior. Oligopolistic markets limit the cooperation of states. Within rules laid down by governments, whether firms survive and prosper depends on their own effort. Firms need not to protect themselves physically against assaults from other firms. They are free to concentrate on their economic interests. As economic entities, however, they live in a self-help world. All want to increase profits. If they run undue risks in the effort to do so, they must expect to suffer the consequences. As William Fellner says, it is “impossible to maximize joint gains without the collusive handling of all relevant variables”. And this can be accomplished only by “complete disarmament of firms in relations to each other”. But cannot sensibly disarm even to increase their profits. This statement qualifies, rather than contradicts, the assumption that firms aim at maximum profits. To maximize profits tomorrow as well as today, firms first have to survive. Pooling all resources implies, again as Fellner puts in, “discounting the future possibilities of all participating firms” (1949, p. 35). But the future cannot be discounted. The relative strength of firms changes over time in ways that cannot be foreseen. Firms are constrained to strike a compromise between maximizing their profits and minimizing the danger of their own demise. Each of two firms may be better off if one of them accepts compensation from the other in return of withdrawing from some part of the market. But a firm that accepts smaller markets, in exchange for larger profits will be gravely disadvantaged if, for example, a price war should break out as part of renewed struggle for markets. If possible, one must resist accepting smaller markets in return for larger profits (…). “It is”, Fellner insists, “not advisable to disarm in relation to one’s rivals” (p. 199). Why not? Because “the potentiality of renewed warfare always exists” (p. 177). Fellner’s reasoning is much like the reasoning that led Lenin to believe that capitalist countries would never be able to cooperate with their mutual enrichment in one vast imperial enterprise. Like nations, oligopolistic firms must be more concerned with relative strength than with absolute advantage.

A state worries about a division of possible gains that may favor others more than itself. That is the first way in which the structure of international politics limits the cooperation of states. A state also worries lest it become dependent on others through cooperative endeavors and exchanges of goods and services. That is the second way in which the structure of international politics limits the cooperation of states. The more a state specialize, the more it relies on others to supply the materials and goods that it is not producing. The larger the state’s imports and exports, the more it depends on others. The world’s well-being would be increased if an ever more elaborate division of labor were developed, but states would thereby place themselves in situations of ever closer interdependence. Some states may not resist that. For small and ill-endowed states the costs of doing so are excessively high. But states that can resist becoming ever more enmeshed with others ordinarily do so in either or moth ways. States that are heavily dependent, or closely interdependent, worry about securing that which they depend on. The high interdependence of states means that the states in question experience, or are subject to, the common vulnerability that high interdependence entails. Like other organizations, states seek to control what they depend on or to lessen the extent of their dependency. This simple thought explains quite a bit of the behavior of the states; their imperial thrusts to widen the scope of their control and their autarchic strivings toward grater self-sufficiency.

Structures encourage certain behaviors and penalize those who do not respond to the encouragement. Nationally, many lament the extreme development of the division of labor, a development that results in the allocation of ever narrower tasks to the individuals. And yet, specialization proceeds, and its extent is a measure of the development of the societies. In a formally organized realm a premium is put on each unit’s being able to specialize in order to increase its value to others in a system of divided labor. The domestic imperative is “specialize”! Internationally, many lament the resources states spend unproductively for their own defense and the opportunities they miss to enhance the welfare of their people through cooperation with other states. And yet the ways of states change little. In an unorganized realm each unit’s incentive is to put itself in a position to be able to take care of itself since no one else can be counted to do so. The international imperative is “take care of yourself”! Some leaders of nations may understand that the well-being of all of them would increase through their participation in a fuller division of labor. But to act on the idea would be to act on a domestic imperative, an imperative that does not run internationally. What one might want to do in absence of structural constraints is different from what one is encouraged to do in their presence. States do not willingly place themselves in situations of increased dependence. In a self-help system, considerations of security subordinate economic gain to political interest.

What each state does for itself is much like what all others are doing. They are denied the advantages that a full division of labor, political as well as economic, would provide. Defense spending, moreover, is unproductive for all and unavoidable for most. Rather than increased well-being, their reward is in the maintenance of their autonomy. States compete, but not by contributing their individual efforts to the joint production of goods for their mutual benefit. Here is a second big difference between international-political and economic system, one which is discussed in part I, section 4, of the next chapter.

 

3. STRUCTURES AND STRATEGIES

 

(Kenneth Waltz: Theory of International Politics; University of California – Berkeley; Addison-Wesley Publishing Company 1979)

 

 

No comments:

Post a Comment