Thursday, March 12, 2020

Томас Хил Грин: ПОЛИТИЧКА ОБЛИГАЦИЈА



LECTURES ON THE PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL OBLIGATION

L. The Right of the State to Punish

183. It is true that when a crime of certain sort, e.g. a cold blooded murder, has been committed, a popular sympathy with the sufferer is excited, which expresses itself in the wish to ‘serve out’ the murderer. This has some resemblance to the desire for personal revenge, but it is really quite different, because not egoistic. Indignation against wrong done to another has nothing in common with desire to revenge a wrong done to oneself. It borrows the language of private revenge, just as the love of God borrows the language of sensuous affection. Such indignation is inseparable from the interest in social well-being, and along with it, is the chief agent in the establishment and maintenance of legal punishment. Law indeed is necessary general, while indignation is particular in its reference; and accordingly, the treatment of any particular crime, so far as determined by law, cannot correspond with the indignation which crime excites, but the law merely determines the general category under which the crime falls, and fixes certain limits to the punishment that may be inflicted under that category. Within those limits, discretion is left to the judge as to the sentence that he passes, and his sentence is in part influenced by the sort of indignation which, in the given state of public sentiment, the crime is calculated to excite; though generally much more by his opinion as to the amount of terror required for the prevention of prevalent crime. Now what is it in punishment that this indignation demands? If not the sole foundation of public punishment, it is yet inseparable from the public interest on which the system of rights, with the corresponding system of punishments protective of rights, depends. In whatever sense then, this indignation demands retribution in punishment, in that sense retribution would seem to be a necessary element in punishment. It demands retribution in the sense of demanding that the criminal should have his due, should be dealt with, according to his deserts, should be punished justly.

184. This is quite a different thing from an equivalence between the amount of suffering inflicted by the criminal and that which he sustains in punishment. The amount of suffering which is caused by any crime is really as incalculable as that which the criminal endures in punishment, whatever the punishment. It is only in a case of death for murder that there is any appearance of equivalence between the two sufferings, and in this case the appearance is quite superficial. The suffering involved in death depends almost entirely on the circumstances, which is absolutely different in the case of the murdered man and in that of the man execute for murder. When a man is imprisoned with hard labor for robbery there is not even an appearance of equivalence of suffering between the crime and the punishment. In what then the justice of a punishment, or its correspondence with the criminal’s deserts consist? It will not do to say that these terms merely represent the result of an association of ideas between the crime and the penalty which are accustomed to see inflicted on it; that society has come to attach certain penalties to certain actions as a result of an experience (1) of suffering and loss cause by these acts, and (2) of the kind of suffering of which the expectation will deter men from doing them; and that these penalties having become customary, the onlookers and the criminal himself, when one of them is inflicted, feel that he has got what was to be expected, and call it his due or desert or a just punishment. If this were the true account of matter, there would be nothing to explain the difference between the emotion excited by the spectacle of a just punishment inflicted, or the demand that it should be inflicted, on the one side, and on the other, that excited by the sight of physical suffering, following according to the usual course of things upon a physical combination of circumstances, or the expectation that such suffering will follow. If it is said that the difference is explained by the fact that in one case both the antecedent (the criminal act) and the consequent, represent voluntary human agency, while in the other – they do not, we reply. Just so, but for that reason, the conception of a punishment, as just differs wholly from any conception of it, that could result either from its being customary, or from the infliction of such punishment having been commonly found a means for protecting us against hurt.

185. The idea of punishment implies, on the side of the person punished, at once a capacity for determination by conception of a common or a public good, or in other words, a practical understanding of the nature of rights, as founded on relation to such public good, and an actual violation of right or omission to fulfill an obligation, the right or obligation being one of which the agent might been aware, and the violation or omission one which he might have prevented. On the side of the authority punishing, it implies equally a conception of right founded on relation on public good, and one which, unlike that on the part of the criminal, is realized in act; a conception of which the punitive act, as founded on a consideration of what is necessary for the maintenance of rights, is the logical expression. A punishment is unjust if either element is absent; if either the act punished is not a violation of known rights or omission to fulfill known obligations of a kind which the agent might have prevented, or the punishment is one that is not required for the maintenance of rights, or (which comes to the same thing) if the ostensible rights for the maintenance of which the punishment is required, are not real rights – not liberties of action, or acquisition which there is any real public interest in maintaining.

186. When the specified conditions of just punishment is fulfilled, the person punished himself recognizes it as just, as he due or desert, and it is so recognized by the onlooker who thinks himself into the situation. The criminal, being susceptible to the idea of public good, and through it of rights, though this idea has not been strong enough to regulate his actions, sees in the punishment its natural expression. He sees that the punishment is his own act, returning on himself, in the sense that it is necessary outcome of his act in a society governed by the conception of rights – a conception which he appreciates, and to which he does involuntary reverence.
It is the outcome of his act, or his act returning upon himself in a different way from that in which a man’s act return on himself when, having misused his body, he is visited according to physical necessity by painful consequences. The cause of the suffering which the act entails, in the one case, is the relation of the act to a society governed by the conception of rights, in the other is not. For that reason, the painful consequence of the act to the doer in one case is, in the other is not, properly a punishment. We do indeed commonly speak of the painful consequences of imprudent or immoral acts (immoral as distinct of illegal) as a punishment of them, but this is either metaphorically, or because we think of the course of the world, as regulated by a divine sovereign, whom we conceive as a maintainer of rights, like the sovereign of the state. We may think of it as divinely regulated, and so regulated with a view to the realization of moral good, but we shall still not be warranted in speaking of the sufferings which follow in the course of nature, upon certain kinds of conduct as punishments, according to the distinctive sense in which crime is punished, unless we suppose the maintenance of rights to be the object of the moral government of the world – which is to put the cart before the horse, for as we have seen, rights are relative to morality, not morality to rights (the ground on which certain liberties of action and acquisition should be guaranteed as rights being that they are conditions of the moral perfection of society).
While there would be reason, then, as against those who say that the punishment of crime is merely preventive, in saying that it is also retributive, if the needed correction of the ‘merely preventive’ doctrine could not be more accurately stated, it would seem that the truth can be more accurately stated by the proposition that punishment is not justified unless it is just, and that is just unless the act punished is an intentional violation of real right, or neglect of real obligation, which the agent could have avoided, i.e. unless the agent knowingly and by intentional act interferes with some freedom of action or acquisition, which there is a public interest in maintaining, and unless the future maintenance of rights requires that the criminal be dealt with, as he is in the punishment.

187. It is clear, however, that this requirement that punishment of crime should be just may be covered by the statement that in its proper nature it is preventive, if the nature of that which is to be prevented by it, is sufficiently defined. Its proper function is in the interest of rights that are genuine (in the sense explained), to prevent actions of the kind described by associating in the mind of every possible doer of them, a certain terror as is necessary on the whole to protect the rights threatened by such action. The whipping of an ill-behaved dog is preventive, but not preventive in the sense in which the punishment of crime is so, because (1) the dog’s ill conduct is not an intentional violation of right, or neglect of a known obligation, the dog having no conception of right or obligation, and (2) for the same reason, the whipping does not lead to the association of terror in minds of other dogs with the violation of rights or other obligations. To shot men down who resist a successful coup d’tat may be effectually preventive of further resistance to the government established by the coup d’tat, but it does not satisfy the true idea of punishment because the terror produced by the massacre is not necessary for the protection of genuine rights – rights founded on public interest. To hang men for sheep-stealing, again, does not satisfy the idea; because, it is a genuine right that the sheep-stealing violates, in a society where there was any decent reconciliation of rights, no such terror as it caused by the punishment of death would be required for protection of the right. It is because the theory that punishment is ‘merely preventive’ favors the notion that the repetition of any action which any sufficient body of men find inconvenient, may justifiably be prevented by any sort of terror that may be convenient for the purpose, that it requires to be guarded by substituting for the qualifying ‘merely’ a statement of what it is which the justifiable punishment prevents, and why it prevents it.

188. But, does our theory after all has been said about the wrongness of punishment that is not just, afford any standard for the apportionment of just punishment, any criterion of the amount of interference with a criminal’s personal right that is appropriate to his crime, except such as is afforded by a prevalent impression among men, as to what is necessary for their security?

(изд. Т.Х. Грин: „Лекции за принципите на политичката облигација“; Batoche books Kitchener 1999)


No comments:

Post a Comment